A report by
a working group of The University of Toronto Joint Centre for Bioethics
Toronto, Canada
This report
is dedicated to the courageous health care workers in Toronto and
around the world who have been affected, became sick or died in
the line of duty caring for patients with SARS.
Table of contents
Executive summary
Major ethical issues and lessons from the Toronto SARS outbreak
1. When public health trumps civil liberties: the ethics of quarantine
2. Naming names, naming communities: privacy of personal information
and public need to know
3. Health care workers' duty to care, and the duty of institutions
to support them
4. Collateral damage: other victims of SARS
5. SARS in a globalized world
Appendix: Decision Tool for Policy Makers in Addressing Future Epidemics
End material
Severe
Acute Respiratory Syndrome (SARS) is a severe form of pneumonia.
This highly contagious disease originated in Guangdong Province
in southern China in the fall of 2002, and began to spread to
a number of countries via people traveling on international
flights during February 2003. The main symptoms of SARS include
both a high fever (over 38 degrees Celsius) and respiratory
problems, including dry cough, shortness of breath or breathing
difficulties. The virus appears to be transmitted through tiny
droplets in the air, but also through contact with contaminated
surfaces. |
Executive
summary
The outbreak
of Severe Acute Respiratory Syndrome (SARS) in the Toronto area
forced hard choices on people in Canada's largest urban area. Medical
and public health communities, federal, provincial and local governments,
and ordinary citizens had to make difficult decisions, often with
limited information and short deadlines. Health care providers were
on the firing line, and were the most affected by the disease.1
Decision makers
had to balance individual freedoms against the common good, fear
for personal safety against the duty to treat the sick and economic
losses against the need to contain the spread of a deadly disease.
At times like this it is necessary to rely both on science and value
systems to guide decisions. The SARS outbreak raised ethical issues
for which Canadian society was not fully prepared. Lessons need
to be learned from this outbreak, to ensure preparedness not only
against the spread of SARS, if it cannot be contained globally,
but also for dealing with epidemics of other diseases.
A working group
from The University of Toronto Joint Centre for Bioethics undertook
to draw ethical lessons from the challenges and responses in Toronto.
The group was composed of nine experts in medical ethics who came
from such disciplines as medicine, surgery, health law, social work,
teaching, nursing and epidemiology. A number of team members were
working in directly affected hospitals, and some were involved in
decision-making regarding the outbreak.
SARS
as a warning
Over the
past 15 years, decisions had to be made about how to react
to cholera in South America, plague in India, Ebola in Zaire,
mad cow disease in Europe, anthrax in the United States, AIDS
throughout the world and the annual waves of influenza. In
fact, the flu may pose the greatest future risk. There were
three influenza pandemics in the Twentieth Century, including
the 1918-1919 Spanish Influenza, which killed more than 20
million people, about double the number of people killed during
the First World War. A number of experts expect another flu
pandemic within a decade.
|
To respond to
future health crises involving highly contagious diseases, an ethical
framework is required. In this report, we develop such a framework
(see appendix), based on five major ethical issues
where SARS forced people, particularly those in the public health
system, to make difficult ethical choices, and we identify 10 associated
key ethical values.
Ten
key ethical values |
|
Individual
liberty |
Privacy |
Protection
of the public from harm |
Protection
of communities from undue stigmatization |
Proportionality |
Duty to
provide care |
Reciprocity |
Equity |
Transparency |
Solidarity |
The five major
ethical issues are:
1. When public
health trumps civil liberties: the ethics of quarantine
There are times
when the interests of protecting public health override some individual
rights, such as freedom of movement. At such times, society has
a duty to inform people of the nature of the threat, be open in
explaining the reasons for over-riding individual freedoms and do
as much as possible to assist those whose rights are being infringed.
2. Naming
names, naming communities: privacy of personal information and public
need to know
While the individual
has a right to privacy, the state may temporarily suspend this privacy
right in case of serious public health risks, when revealing private
medical information would help protect public health. As a general
rule, the privacy and confidentiality of individuals should be protected
unless a well-defined public health goal can be achieved by the
release of this information.
3. Health
care workers' duty to care and the duty of institutions to support
them
Health care
professionals have a duty to care for the sick. During infectious
epidemics this must be done in a way that minimizes the possibility
of their transmitting diseases to the uninfected. Institutions have
a reciprocal duty to support and protect health care workers to
help them cope with very stressful situations, and recognize their
contributions.
4. Collateral
damage: other victims of SARS
Severe restrictions
on entry to SARS-affected hospitals meant that many people were
denied medical care, sometimes for severe illnesses. As a result,
patients in hospital, with or without SARS, and their families suffered
from lack of contact due to the elimination of visits for a period
of time. It is essential to maintain an equitable balance among
the interests of those patients with or at risk of SARS, and those
who are sick with other diseases, and need urgent treatment.
5. SARS in
a globalized world
SARS is a wakeup
call about global interdependence, and the increasing risk of the
emergence and rapid spread of infectious diseases. There is a need
to strengthen the global health system to cope with infectious diseases
in the interests of all, including those in the richer and poorer
nations. This will require global solidarity and cooperation in
the interest of everyone's health.
Major ethical
issues and lessons from the Toronto SARS outbreak
In analyzing
each of the five major ethical issues the team looked at the underlying
ethical values, and drew lessons from how each of the five issues
was addressed. The case studies represent an amalgam of experience.
In most cases, we did not use real names, in order to respect the
privacy of individuals who were not identified in media coverage.
1.
When public health trumps civil liberties: the ethics of quarantine
The issue
"Jean,"
a clerk in a medical office, is asked by Toronto's public health
department to remain at home in quarantine for 10 days because of
possible exposure to SARS. She wants to comply, but fears this could
cost both her job and her apartment.
"Michel"
is in quarantine because a family member has contracted SARS, and
he may have been infected. A close family friend has died from causes
not associated with the SARS epidemic, and "Michel" is
torn between wanting to attend the funeral and his duty to respect
the quarantine order.
Contagious diseases,
like wars, test the limits of freedom in societies. SARS is a sobering
reminder that the interests of the individual must on occasion be
tempered by the best interests of the community. In Toronto, thousands
were placed in quarantine, often at home, in order to protect millions
of people not only in the city but around the world from possible
exposure to a deadly disease.
Ethical values
Individual
liberty. In Canada as in many other liberal democracies, the
idea of virtually unfettered personal freedom has become a strongly
held value. In recent years, we have faced a number of serious public
health issues-including tuberculosis, AIDS and influenza-that required
decisions that seek to balance the rights of the individual and
the common good of society. SARS has created an even sharper test
of which rights should prevail at what time. The law allows individual
rights to be overridden for the common good, under defined circumstances.
The goal is to do this in an ethical and even-handed manner so that
people are not unfairly or disproportionately harmed by such measures.
Protection
of the public from harm. When clear, serious and imminent harm
to the population is demonstrable, public health authorities have
a duty to restrict certain individual rights in the interest of
the health and well-being of the community.2 In turn,
citizens have a civic duty to comply with such restrictions for
the common good.
Proportionality.
When protecting many from harm is ethically necessary, and when
the use of public health powers to achieve those goals can be justified,
authorities must also protect individuals from needless coercion.
Restrictions of liberty must be relevant, legitimate and necessary.
They must be exercised by people with legitimate authority, and
those people should use the least restrictive methods that are reasonably
available. Such restrictions should be applied without discrimination.
Transparency.
In modern democratic societies, all legitimate stakeholders need
to be properly informed about the issues, including the risks and
benefits of various options, and have input into discussions on
issues that affect them, particularly those that affect their health,
well-being and personal liberty.
Reciprocity.
Society has a duty to see that those quarantined receive adequate
care, are not kept in quarantine for excessively long periods, and
are not abandoned or psychosocially isolated. There may also be
a need to eliminate economic barriers, such as loss of income, which
would otherwise prevent someone from obeying a quarantine order.3
Lessons
learned
There are times
when the interests of protecting public health override some individual
rights, such as freedom of movement. At such times, society has
a duty to fully inform people of the situation, be open in explaining
the reasons and do as much as possible to assist those whose rights
are being infringed.
Under the ethical
value of proportionality, authorities have the right to impose quarantine
and isolation, but it is preferable, as was the case in Toronto,
to use voluntary measures first. When people are fully informed,
and see that they are being treated as fairly as possible, it is
likely that voluntarism will prevail in times of emergency. In fact,
most people in Toronto cooperated with restrictions. More coercive
measures (such as detention orders or surveillance technology) should
be reserved for those cases where non-compliance is documented,
and potential harm to others is anticipated. Evidence indicates
that most people can deal with a quarantine of about 10 days. In
cases of incubation periods longer than 10 days, the enforcement
of quarantine becomes more difficult. In the Toronto SARS outbreak,
a 10-day quarantine was used.
Under the ethical
value of transparency, public health authorities must regularly
communicate the reasons for the imposition of quarantine or isolation,
the nature of the potential harm, attendant risks to various groups
of people, and publicly communicate the necessity for various restrictions
on personal liberty.
Under the ethical
value of reciprocity, people placed in quarantine and isolation
should be assisted to overcome the hardships imposed. This will
also facilitate compliance. The assistance should include ensuring
that they have access to food, help with problem solving around
shelter for other family members, alternative medical care, job
protection and phone calls for support and comfort. In the Toronto
case, volunteer agencies and organizations such as Meals on Wheels,
the Red Cross and the Toronto Public Health department, have helped
people in home quarantine to live as normal a life as possible.
Governments indicated that people are not to suffer employment loss
or discrimination, and that waiting times for benefits from employment
insurance would be reduced to recognize the hardship imposed by
quarantine.
Quarantine
and isolation
Both terms
refer to restrictions of movement and physical separation
from others of people who may have been exposed to a contagious
disease. Quarantine is applied to people who show no symptoms
of the disease. Isolation refers to those showing symptoms.
|
2.
Naming names, naming communities: privacy of personal information
and public need to know
The issue
"June,"
a nurse at a downtown Toronto hospital that was affected by SARS,
is feeling a bit unwell, but her temperature, a key sign of SARS,
is normal. She weighs the risk of possibly having the disease against
the costs of losing pay if she does not show up, and worries about
placing a burden of extra work on her colleagues. "June"
takes the GO commuter train to work. Medical officials fear she
might have SARS, and have infected a group of commuters, spreading
the disease into the community, where it might be impossible to
control. They choose not to name her on the grounds that this would
serve no purpose because she has not tested positive for SARS, but
they do warn people on that train car to be checked in case they
develop SARS.
In contrast,
the name of the woman who was identified as accidentally bringing
SARS to Canada is made public. Kwan Sui-chu, 78, and her husband
visit Hong Kong in February, where she contracts the disease. Upon
her return home to Toronto, she passes it to her family, starting
the chain of contamination. She dies at home, but her son goes to
hospital for treatment of fever and a cough, and spreads the disease
to other people, beginning a series of infections in the city.
The issue of
naming names applied across the spectrum from the individual to
global levels. Health and government officials had to weigh the
benefits and harms of exposing people, communities and whole countries
to discrimination. In the case of China, the government decided
not to release information about the seriousness of the SARS outbreak
until the spring, several months after the initial outbreak in Guangdong
Province. In Toronto, publicly linking of SARS with someone who
had travelled from China stigmatized the Chinese community, and
led to a precipitous fall in business for Chinese enterprises, particularly
restaurants. When Toronto was put on a do-not-visit list by the
World Health Organization, it had a huge economic impact in terms
of lost visits and tourism.
Ethical values
Privacy and
confidentiality of health information. Individuals have a right
to control the amount of information about themselves to which others
have access. Health authorities are bound to protect confidentiality
as much as possible. However, the right to privacy is not absolute.
The challenge is to balance the costs of releasing information about
individuals and communities against the benefits of reducing a public
health risk.
Protection
of the public health. As is the case with quarantine, protection
of the public health may limit the individual's right to privacy
and confidentiality of health information.
Proportionality.
In order to release private and confidential information, health
officials must be able to argue that the protection of public health
could not be achieved by less intrusive measures, and this will
not often be the case. For example, in the case of "June"
public health authorities were right to announce that a patient
with SARS traveled on the commuter train in a particular car at
a particular time, and to encourage others in that car to contact
public health authorities. There would have been no added protection
of the public health by releasing the person's name or photograph.
Transparency.
Honest reporting about an emerging epidemic and the numbers of people
affected does not violate an individual's right to privacy of medical
information. Arguably, the reluctance of Chinese authorities to
release information about the seriousness of SARS to the World Health
Organization prolonged the epidemic.
Protection
of communities from undue stigmatization. Particular caution
should be taken not to unduly stigmatize communities through the
release of information.
Lessons learned
There was a
tendency to name names more freely at the start of the Toronto outbreak,
but authorities became more protective of people's privacy, when
it became evident that there was no public good served in releasing
names of those affected. It appeared that the Chinese community
was being stigmatized without producing any public health benefit.
As a general
rule, the privacy and confidentiality of individuals should be protected
unless a well-defined public health goal can be achieved by the
release of this information to the general public.
3. Health
care workers' duty to care, and the duty of institutions to support
them
The issue
"Mary,"
a nurse in the Intensive Care Unit, is afraid that when she goes
to work she will have to care for SARS patients and may become infected.
Her husband asks her to call in sick, pleading that it is her duty
as the mother of three small children not to risk giving them SARS.
"Mary" feels torn. She feels her primary responsibility
is to do everything in her power to protect her children. At the
same time, "Mary" has a strong commitment to her profession,
and the family needs her income. She has studied hard to become
a staff nurse, and is aware of the importance the hospital places
on good attendance. Her salary is affected by calling in sick. She
also wants to support her colleagues on the front lines by going
to work.
For the first
time in more than a generation, Toronto health care practitioners
were forced to weigh serious and imminent health risks to themselves
and their families against their obligation to care for the sick.
This generation of clinicians had entered their profession in an
era when there was little expectation of facing deadly infectious
diseases that had no ready cure. Suddenly, a large number of health
care workers, particularly nurses and doctors, faced tough choices
about how much risk to take. They had to put their lives at risk
to help others. Dozens of medical workers, most of them nurses,
caught SARS during their work. The most public example of the sacrifice
by a health care worker was the untimely and tragic death of Dr.
Carlo Urbani, who was infected in Vietnam.
SARS imposed
great stresses on health care workers. They feared contagion for
themselves and their families, and being shunned by others in case
they were infectious. They suffered from disrupted routines, and
loss of work for those who were quarantined or were unable to work
because their hospitals had cut back on admitting non-SARS cases.
Many health professionals had to wear cumbersome and very uncomfortable
equipment to protect themselves, causing discomfort and hampering
their ability to work. This also reduced the human contact with
sick and dying patients.
Ethical
values
Duty to care.
Health care professionals have a duty to care based on several ethical
considerations. The first is "virtue ethics" which means
being of good character. The health care professional is seen as
a "good person" who may be relied upon to demonstrate
altruism by putting the patient's needs foremost. When they enter
their profession, physicians take an oath that they will be competent,
and will use their skills in caring for the sick.
As one member
of this panel put it, "when we sign on as health care providers
we must accept the risks. Firefighters don't get to pick whether
they will attend at a particularly bad fire, and cops don't get
to select which dark alleys they walk down. To me it would be unethical
to deny care even if there is 'somewhere else' that could take that
patient."
Reciprocity.
Just as health care professionals have a duty to care, society and
institutions have a reciprocal duty to assist these professionals.
This includes providing information for staff so they can fully
understand the risks, and having policies that support safety practices.
These policies should avoid penalization from either a financial
or other standpoint for events, such as loss of work that is not
the fault of the employees. As part of this behaviour, institutions
must practice transparency, and this will foster trust in the organizations
by their staff.
Lessons learned
While health
care professionals have a duty to care for the sick, this must be
tempered by a duty to care for themselves in order to remain well
enough to be able to carry out their duties.4 To extend
the analogy introduced above, the fireman would not knowingly jump
into a burning inferno. Where to draw the line between role-related
professional responsibilities and undue risk is a question our working
group struggled with, but did not fully resolve.
Health care
institutions have a duty to provide the supports that enable employees
to do their jobs effectively and as safely as possible. Information
needs to be shared in a timely way so that health care workers are
fully informed, and enjoy a climate of trust in their place of employment.
Institutions
need clear guidelines in place so employees know what is expected
of them, and what help they may expect. In addition, employment
policies need to ensure that staff are rewarded rather than penalized
for following safe practices such as staying home when they are
ill. In future cases, hospitals might be able to make better use
of staff in helping isolated patients make contact with their families.
For example, instead of sending health care workers home with no
work, they could be given the job of phoning patients and their
families to provide information and support.
Finally, there
is a duty for the public and persons in authority to recognize the
heroism of front-line medical workers during the SARS outbreak.
In Toronto, most health workers responded courageously
4.
Collateral damage: other victims of SARS
The issue
"Anne"
has breast cancer. Her surgery is postponed during the SARS outbreak,
increasing anxiety in her and her family about the spread of her
disease.
"Tom",
who at 58 has valiantly fought a brain tumour for 13 years, including
three major brain surgeries, is admitted to the hospital with an
urgent but unrelated condition. He starts to deteriorate, and it
appears that the inevitable victory by his tumour is close at hand.
"Jane", his wife and soul-mate, who has been faithfully
and constantly by his side through good times and bad, is not allowed
into the hospital to be with her very sick husband. She waits frantically
by the phone, and the surgeon spends what little time he can spare
to keep her informed.
There was a
great amount of "collateral damage" to a wide range of
people who did not have SARS. Many people with other serious conditions
had surgeries cancelled because some hospitals were considered contaminated
areas, and some of these people died. Some of those patients died
before receiving treatment. At the University Health Network alone,
which includes Toronto General, Toronto Western and Princess Margaret
hospitals, 1,050 surgical procedures were cancelled because of SARS.
This included transplants, cancer and heart surgeries, hip and knee
replacements and lens implants. In addition, there were cancellations
of radiation, chemotherapy, dialysis, physiotherapy and other treatments.
The strict "no visitors" policies during the early part
of the outbreak meant that both SARS and non-SARS patients in hospitals
were cut off from their families and friends. Those who were admitted,
with or without SARS, suffered loss of contact and emotional support
from family and friends as hospitals closed their doors to visitors.5
Ethical
values
Equity.
In the SARS emergency, authorities faced hard choices in deciding
which medical services to maintain and which to place on hold. They
had to weigh risks, benefits and opportunity costs. It is necessary
for such hard decisions to be made in a fair manner, including appropriate
access to limited resources. There needs to be equity between SARS
and non-SARS patients.
Lessons learned
In the case
of an epidemic, it is important to control the spread of the disease,
but as much attention should be paid to the rights of the non-infected
patients who need urgent medical care. There may be as many people
who died from other illnesses and could not get into hospital as
there were who died from SARS.
Equity is required in the amount of attention given to a wide array
of people, including patients with and without SARS. Accountability
for making reasonable decisions, transparency and fairness are expected.
There is a need to communicate accurate information to the public,
putting the risks and benefits of various strategies and decisions
in focus.
5.
SARS in a globalized world
The issue
In Guangdong
province in rural China it is early winter and "Mr. Li,"
a farmer, comes down with a severe respiratory infection. His son
leaves for Beijing, carrying the SARS microbe and its descendants
on a journey that will span the world. One of its major destinations
is Toronto, where thousands will be forced into quarantine to stop
the spread of SARS.
In Geneva,
the World Health Organization weighs the risks of SARS spreading
from Toronto. WHO issues an unprecedented travel advisory in April,
warning people not to go to Toronto unless necessary, in order to
minimize the risk that Toronto could export the disease to countries
not equipped to handle it. One week later, WHO lifts the travel
warning, saying that the magnitude of the problem in Toronto has
decreased, and there is no evidence that the city is exporting SARS
cases.
In a number
of institutions, scientists race to break the genetic code of the
SARS virus, and then to patent it. The way the patents are exercised
will have global implications for who can get access to such results,
and to resulting products, such as vaccines.
Globalization
is associated with increases in travel and transportation, communications
and the sharing of cultures. As a result of the growing web of interconnections,
microbes have an easier ride than ever. In the Middle Ages, it took
three years for the plague to spread from Asia to the western reaches
of Europe. The SARS virus, crossed from Hong Kong to Toronto in
about 15 hours.
Ethical values
Solidarity.
One of the great challenges of the 21st century is to understand
the interconnections between globalization and health, and to find
ways of narrowing global health disparities in different regions.
A new global health ethic based on solidarity could help make the
world a more stable place. Solidarity means feeling one has common
cause with others who are less powerful, wealthy, or healthy. Infectious
diseases can spread in either direction between poor, rural areas
and rich urban areas, anywhere in the world.
There is also
a need for transparency, honesty and good communications on health
issues at a global level so that people and nations can take appropriate
steps to protect themselves.
Lessons learned
It is clear
that while health is treated as a national, regional or local responsibility,
it must be seen and acted upon as a global public good. This calls
for new ways of thinking and acting. Distinctions between domestic
and foreign policy have become blurred, and public health, even
in the most privileged nations, is closely linked to health and
disease in impoverished countries. Now more than ever, local action
must be linked to global action. We need a new mindset to improve
health and deal with threats to health globally.
There is also
a need for transparency, honesty and good communications on health
issues. It is no longer acceptable for countries to hide health
information that can protect others. Such sharing is part of maintaining
a global public good of health protection. A new governance mechanism
is needed for global surveillance of infectious diseases. The world
should consider strengthening the role of the World Health Organization,
giving it the right to gather information, communicate it, and to
help countries deal with outbreaks.
There is also
a need to strengthen the global health system to cope with infectious
diseases. Countries invest large amounts in national laboratories
for disease control, but relatively little in international organizations
such as the WHO.
There are some
pressing global needs. Countries need adequate public health laboratories,
surveillance and epidemiological capacity, information systems for
data gathering, storage and analysis, and health communication capabilities
linked to international obligation to report. The world needs standardization
and harmonization of standards and criteria. It also needs to increase
and strengthen the capacity to respond to outbreaks, especially
in developing countries. This requires training in public health,
and the resources to put enough health workers into place.
SARS
and intellectual property rights
The patenting
of materials and processes is an important part of globalization,
and SARS rapidly became part of that process. The genome sequence
of the virus thought to be responsible for SARS was published
by the British Columbia Cancer Agency, based on samples taken
from SARS patients in Toronto. Several groups are seeking
to patent the genetic code of the virus. The implications
will be seen over time. A patent holder may commercialize
the research findings in order to make diagnostic products
in the short term, and perhaps therapeutic agents and vaccines
in the longer term. The patent holder may also opt to make
the patented findings freely available for the public good.
Few jurisdictions have intellectual property regimes that
are set up to address ethical or policy issues. So long as
the patent criteria are met, a patent will be issued.
|
Appendix: Decision
Tool for Policy Makers in Addressing Future Epidemics
|
1. Civil
liberties and quarantine |
2. Naming
names and the right to privacy |
3. Duty
to care |
4. Collateral
damage |
5. Global
concerns |
Individual
Liberty |
Individual
rights can be overridden for common good. Must be ethical, even-handed
so no one is unfairly harmed. |
|
|
|
|
Public
Protection |
Authorities
have duty to restrict certain rights to safeguard public health.
Citizens must comply for common good. |
Protection
of public health may limit individual right to privacy and confidentiality
of health information. |
|
|
|
Proportionality |
Restrictions
of liberty must be legitimate and necessary, exercised by people
with authority using least restrictive methods available. |
Health
officials releasing confidential information must be able to
argue that protection of the public health could not be achieved
by less intrusive measures. |
|
|
|
Reciproity |
Those quarantined
receive adequate care, should not be kept in quarantine for
excessively long periods, abandoned or psychologically isolated.
Economic barriers, such as loss of income, may have to be eliminated. |
|
Society
and institutions have a reciprocal duty to assist health care
professionals, providing information so staff can understand
risks, and having policies that support safety practices. |
|
|
Transparency |
All stakeholders
to be properly informed about issues, including risks and benefits
of various options, and have input on issues that affect them. |
Honest
reporting about an emerging epidemic and the numbers of people
affected should not violate an individual's right to privacy
of medical information. |
|
|
|
Privacy |
|
Individuals
have a right to privacy but this is not absolute. Harms of releasing
information must be balanced against benefits of reducing health
risk. |
|
|
|
Protection
Against Stigmatization |
|
Caution
should be taken not to unduly stigmatize communities through
the release of information. |
|
|
|
Duty to
Provide Care |
|
|
Health
professionals have a duty to care based on several ethical considerations,
such as "virtue ethics" which means being of good
character. |
|
|
Equity
|
|
|
|
In an emergency,
authorities face hard choices about which services to maintain
and which to place on hold. People want these decisions to be
made in a fair manner, including appropriate access to limited
resources. There needs to be equity between SARS and non-SARS
patients. |
|
Solidarity |
|
|
|
|
A new global
health ethic based on solidarity could help make a more stable
world. Solidarity means feeling one has common cause with others
who are less powerful, wealthy, or healthy. |
End material
About this
report
As the dimensions
of the SARS outbreak in Toronto and globally became clear, The University
of Toronto Joint Centre for Bioethics, undertook to draw ethical
lessons from the challenges and responses faced in Toronto. We hope
this will assist the medical communities, governments, employers
and citizens around the world to be better prepared to deal not
only with this disease but with other outbreaks that threaten our
health, economic well-being and quality of life.
This report
is from a working group of nine experts in medical ethics who came
from such disciplines as medicine, surgery, health law, social work,
teaching, nursing and epidemiology. Some members of the group were
involved in decision-making regarding the outbreak. The group met
almost across the street from one of the affected hospitals, and
one member of the team had to participate by telephone in the early
stages, because of a ban on attending meetings for people who had
been in high-risk medical areas.
About University
of Toronto Joint Centre for Bioethics
Innovative.
Interdisciplinary. International. Improving health care through
bioethics.
The Joint
Centre for Bioethics (JCB), a partnership between the University
of Toronto and twelve hospitals, provides leadership in bioethics
research, education, and clinical activities. Its vision is to be
a model of interdisciplinary collaboration in order to create new
knowledge and improve practices with respect to bioethics. The JCB
does not advocate positions on specific issues, although its individual
members may do so.
The goals of
the Centre are to:
- Foster interdisciplinary
research and scholarship, link education to research, and disseminate
research findings to improve policies and practices.
- Support undergraduate,
graduate and postgraduate educational programs in bioethics.
- Support clinical
ethics activities including continuing education for health care
providers, ethics committees, ethics consultation, and projects
to address specific issues arising in JCB hospitals.
- Foster collegial
discussion of bioethics issues throughout JCB participating institutions,
and to serve as a resource for the media, policymakers, and community
groups.
The JCB is a collaborating centre for bioethics for the World
Health Organization.
For more information:
http://www.utoronto.ca/jcb/
Members of
the working group
Solomon R.
Benatar
Solomon R. Benatar is Professor of Medicine and Founding Director
of the University of Cape Town's Bioethics Centre. He was Chairman
of the university's Department of Internal Medicine, and Chief Physician
at Groote Schuur Hospital from 1980-1999. Dr. Benatar is Visiting
Professor in Public Health Sciences and Medicine at the University
of Toronto. His current research interests include International
Health and the implications of Globalization for global health in
the future.
Mark Bernstein
Mark Bernstein is a neurosurgeon at the Toronto Western Hospital,
University Health Network, which was a "hot spot" in the
recent SARS outbreak. He has written on the impacts of SARS on medical
staff, patients and the community. Dr. Bernstein is Professor in
the Department of Surgery at the University of Toronto and has recently
completed a Masters in Health Science in Bioethics at the Joint
Center for Bioethics at the University of Toronto. His areas of
interest in bioethics include medical error, surgical innovation,
surgical education, research ethics, and priority setting.
Abdallah
S. Daar
Abdallah S. Daar is Professor of Public Health Sciences and of Surgery
at the University of Toronto, where he is also Director of the Program
in Applied Ethics and Biotechnology at the Joint Centre for Bioethics.
Dr. Daar is a Fellow of the New York Academy of Sciences, and is
on the Ethics Committee of the (International) Transplantation Society
and that of the Human genome Organization. His current research
interests are in the exploration of how genomics and other biotechnologies
can be used effectively to ameliorate global health inequities.
Bernard Dickens
Bernard Dickens is a professor of health law and policy at the University
of Toronto. Professor Dickens is a legal articles editor, serves
as a member of the editorial boards of several journals legal and
medical journals, and has been involved in a wide variety of organizations
in the field of medical jurisprudence. He has been a director and
president of the American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics, and
is a Fellow of the Royal Society of Medicine (London) and the Royal
Society of Canada.
Susan MacRae
Sue MacRae is a bioethicist and Deputy Director of the University
of Toronto Joint Centre for Bioethics. She has worked as a nurse
in Calgary, as a clinical ethics fellow, program coordinator and
ethics consultant through the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical
Ethics in Chicago and as a research fellow in patient-centered care
at the Picker Institute in Boston. She explores links between bioethics
and quality in the current health care system. She provided leadership
and support to the Joint Centre for Bioethics and affiliated hospital
Bioethicists during the SARS outbreak.
Peter A.
Singer
Peter A. Singer is the Sun Life Financial Chair in Bioethics, Director
of the University of Toronto Joint Centre for Bioethics, and Program
Leader of the Canadian Program on Genomics and Global Health. Dr.
Singer directs the World Health Organization Collaborating Centre
for Bioethics at the University of Toronto. He is also Professor
of Medicine and practices Internal Medicine at Toronto Western Hospital.
He is a member of the Scientific Advisory Board of the Bill and
Melinda Gates Foundation Grand Challenges for Global Health Initiative
and the Ethics Committee of the British Medical Journal, and he
is a Director of The Change Foundation and the Canadian Bacterial
Diseases Network. His current research focus is global health ethics.
Ross Upshur
Ross Upshur is a family physician at Sunnybrook and Women's College
Health Sciences Centre, assistant professor of Family and Community
Medicine and Public Health Sciences and member of the Joint Centre
for Bioethics at the University of Toronto. Dr. Upshur is a community
medicine specialist and researcher with graduate training in philosophy
and epidemiology. During the SARS epidemic, the family practice
clinic was virtually closed, so he worked in York Region with the
public health department in a variety of capacities including outbreak
management and epidemiological analysis.
Linda Wright
Linda Wright is Bioethicist at University Health Network, which
comprises Toronto General Hospital, Toronto Western Hospital and
Princess Margaret Hospital, where several SARS patients were treated.
She has practiced social work in child care and medical settings,
and her professional work has included establishing ethical guidelines
for the care of living organ donors. She is the Past President of
the International Society of Transplant Social Workers and ethics
section editor of the journal Progress in Transplantation.
Randi Zlotnik
Shaul
Randi Zlotnik Shaul is a bioethicist at The Hospital for Sick Children.
Dr. Shaul has degrees in political theory and law, and has studied
the ethical, legal and economic issues around resource allocation
in the medical field. She has published in the area of health law
and priority setting, and is especially interested in clinical ethics
and the role of law in addressing bioethical challenges.
This paper was
produced with the assistance of Michael Keating, a Toronto writer
with a background in risk communications.
Grant support:
Peter A Singer is a Distinguished Investigator and Ross Upshur is
a New Investigator of the Canadian Institutes of Health Research.
This research was supported by the Canadian Program on Genomics
and Global Health (www.geneticsethics.net), which is funded in part
by Genome Canada through the Ontario Genomics Institute.
Address for
correspondence: Peter A. Singer, University of Toronto Joint Centre
for Bioethics, 88 College St., Toronto, Canada M5G 1L4. Email: peter.singer@utoronto.ca.
|