In Canada, one of the major issues surrounding the concept of freedom of expression is whether pornographic material should be censored to prevent its use and distribution, or whether pornographic material that is both potentially harmful and exploitative should be regulated in a post-hoc fashion through the laying of charges of obscenity. Perhaps the most poignant debate surrounds pornographic materials that involve children.
During the 1980s and early 1990s, six Ministers of Justice were involved in drafting amendments to the Criminal Code aimed at preventing the distribution of pornographic material, but none succeeded in producing legislation that seemed to strike an acceptable balance between freedom of expression and the prevention of harm. With new methods of distributing pornographic materials through the internet becoming available, the pressure was mounting for the federal government to take action. Finally in 1993, as part of its law-and-order pre-election positioning, the Conservative government pushed through Parliament amendments to the Criminal Code that made it a criminal offence to distribute or even to possess pornographic materials involving children.
The purpose of this legislation was to prevent the exploitation of children. Some critics thought that the legislation was over-broad, unnecessarily interfering with freedom of expression and privacy. For example, some thought that the legislation might criminalize the possession of family photographs showing children in the bathtub.
In the late 1990s, John Robin Sharpe of Vancouver was charged twice with possession of pornographic materials, and with possession of these materials for the purposes of distribution. Rather than plead guilty, Sharpe decided to make the argument in court that the legislation intended to protect children was over-broad, unnecessarily interfering with his privacy and his freedom of expression. Both the trial court judge and the majority of the panel in the B.C. Court of Appeal agreed with Sharpe, and the case was heard at the Supreme Court of Canada in January of 2000. The Court released its decision a little over a year later.
The seven-judge panel upheld the 1993 amendments to the
Criminal Code, and sent Sharpe back for trial. Four of the seven
judges read in two restrictions to the 1993 amendments. They declared
that the legislation would not be construed so as to apply to "(1) self-created
expressive material: i.e., any written material or visual representation
created by the accused alone, and held by the accused alone,
exclusively for his or her own personal use; and (2)
private recordings of lawful sexual activity: i.e., any visual recording,
created by or depicting the accused, provided it does not depict unlawful
sexual activity and is held by the accused exclusively for private use."
(para. 115)
The reaction of the media to this decision has been mixed. The Globe and Mail seemed to support the view that the Sharpe decision is another indication of the judicial restraint being exercised by the McLaughlin court. The National Post, however, ran commentary critical of the majority decision as being too activist because of the restrictions that the Court read into the legislation, and preferring the more deferential stance of the three-judge minority led by L'Heureux-Dubé. In general, commentators in the justice system seemed pleased with the decision. Very few thought that the restrictions read in by the majority would hamper any of the current prosecutions or investigations related to child pornography.
Here are some excerpts from the majority decision, which was penned by Chief Justice Beverly McLaughlin. (The numbered paragraphs used by the court are shown at the beginning of each paragraph, beginning with paragraph 20.)
* * * * * * * * * * *
20 Reflecting these issues, the constitutional questions have been stated as follows:
1 Does s. 163.1(4) of the Criminal Code, R.S.C.
1985, c. C-46, violate s. 2(b)
of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms?
2 If s. 163.1(4) of the Criminal Code infringes
s. 2(b) of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms, is s. 163.1(4) a reasonable
limit prescribed by
law as can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic
society for the
purposes of s. 1 of the Charter?
3 Does s. 163.1(4) of the Criminal Code, R.S.C.
1985, c. C-46, violate s. 7 of
the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms?
4 If s. 163.1(4) of the Criminal Code, R.S.C.
1985, c. C-46, infringes s. 7 of
the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, is s. 163.1(4)
a reasonable limit
prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in
a free and democratic
society for the purposes of s. 1 of the Charter?
V. Analysis
A. The Values at Stake
21 Among the most fundamental rights possessed
by Canadians is freedom of
expression. It makes possible our liberty, our
creativity and our democracy.
It does this by protecting not only "good" and
popular expression, but also
unpopular or even offensive expression. The
right to freedom of expression
rests on the conviction that the best route to truth,
individual flourishing and
peaceful coexistence in a heterogeneous society in which
people hold divergent
and conflicting beliefs lies in the free flow of ideas
and images. If we do not
like an idea or an image, we are free to argue against
it or simply turn away.
22 Nevertheless, freedom of expression
is not absolute. Our constitution
recognizes that Parliament or a provincial legislature
can sometimes limit some
forms of expression. Overarching considerations,
like the prevention of hate
that divides society as in Keegstra, supra, or the prevention
of harm that
threatens vulnerable members of our society as in Butler,
supra, may justify
prohibitions on some kinds of expression in some circumstances.
24 The law challenged in this appeal engages
mainly the justification of
self-fulfilment. Child pornography does not generally
contribute to the search
for truth or to Canadian social and political discourse.
Some question whether
it engages even the value of self-fulfilment, beyond
the base aspect of sexual
exploitation. The concern in this appeal, however,
is that the law may
incidentally catch forms of expression that more seriously
implicate
self-fulfilment and that do not pose a risk of harm to
children.
26 However, the private nature of much child
pornography cuts two ways. It engages the fundamental
right to freedom of
thought. But at the same time, the clandestine nature
of incitement, attitudinal
change, grooming and seduction associated with child
pornography contributes to
the harm it may cause children, rather than reduces it.
28 However, possession
of child pornography contributes to the market for child
pornography, a market
which in turn drives production involving the exploitation
of children.
Possession of child pornography may facilitate the seduction
and grooming of
victims and may break down inhibitions or incite potential
offences.
30 [Sharpe] suggests rather
that the limitation s. 163.1(4) imposes on free expression
must fail because the
law catches material that poses no risk of harm to children
and because the
links between possession of child pornography and harm
to children are weak.
33 If a legislative provision can be read both in
a way that is constitutional and in a
way that is not, the former reading should be adopted...
34 Parliament's main purpose in passing the
child pornography law was to
prevent harm to children by banning the production, distribution
and possession
of child pornography, and by sending a message to Canadians
"that children need
to be protected from the harmful effects of child sexual
abuse and exploitation
and are not appropriate sexual partners": House of Commons
Debates, 3rd Sess.,
34th Parl., vol. XVI, June 3, 1993, at p. 20328.
37 (1) does "person" apply only to actual,
as opposed to imaginary
persons; and (2) does it include the person who possesses
the material?
38 The first issue is important because it
governs whether the prohibition on
possession is confined to representations of actual persons,
or whether it
extends to drawings from the imagination, cartoons, or
computer generated
composites. The available evidence suggests that
explicit sexual materials can
be harmful whether or not they depict actual children.
Moreover, with the
quality of contemporary technology, it can be very difficult
to distinguish a
"real" person from a computer creation or composite.
Interpreting "person" in
accordance with Parliament's purpose of criminalizing
possession of material
that poses a reasoned risk of harm to children, it seems
that it should include
visual works of the imagination as well as depictions
of actual people.
Notwithstanding the fact that "person" in the charging
section and in s.
163.1(1)(b) refers to a flesh-and-blood person, I conclude
that "person" in s.
163.1(1)(a) includes both actual and imaginary human
beings.
41 However, this age limit extends the reach
of the
law to material beyond the ordinary conception of child
pornography. For
example, it raises the possibility that teenagers, perhaps
even married
teenagers, could be charged and imprisoned for taking
and keeping photos or
videos of themselves engaged in lawful sexual acts, even
if those materials were
intended exclusively for their own personal use.
This prohibition engages the
value of self-fulfilment and may be difficult to link
to a reasoned risk of harm
to children, again raising particularly troubling constitutional
concerns.
45 This suggests that the law catches only depictions
of sexual
intercourse and other non-trivial sexual acts.
51 Family photos of naked children, viewed
objectively, generally do not have
as their "dominant characteristic" the depiction of a
sexual organ or anal
region "for a sexual purpose". .... Absent evidence
indicating a dominant prurient
purpose, a photo of a child in the bath will not be caught.
54 The second category of child pornography
caught by s. 163.1(1) is "any
written material or visual representation that advocates
or counsels sexual
activity with a person under the age of eighteen years
that would be an offence
under this Act".
55 This section is more limited than the definition
of visual pornography in
s. 163.1(1)(a), which captures sexual "representations"
of children. Section
163.1(1)(b) is confined to material relating to activity
that would be a crime
under the Criminal Code. Moreover, it is confined
to material that "counsels"
or "advocates" such crimes. On its face,
it appears to be aimed at combating
written and visual material that actively promotes the
commission of sexual
offences with children.
56 The mere description of the criminal act is not
caught. Rather, the prohibition is against material
that, viewed objectively,
sends the message that sex with children can and should
be pursued.
57 Without suggesting that the distinction
is easy to apply in practice, a
purposive approach appears to exclude many of the alleged
examples of the law's
overbreadth. For instance, works aimed at description
and exploration of
various aspects of life that incidentally touch on illegal
acts with children
are unlikely to be caught. While Nabokov's Lolita, Boccaccio's
Decameron, and
Plato's Symposium portray or discuss sexual activities
with children, on an
objective view they cannot be said to advocate or counsel
such conduct in the
sense of actively inducing or encouraging it.
Nor would the section catch
political advocacy for lowering the age of consent because
such advocacy would
not promote the commission of an offence but the amendment
of the law.
Likewise, an anthropological work discussing the sexual
practices of adolescents
in other cultures and describing such adolescents as
well-adjusted and healthy
would not be caught because it would be merely descriptive
as opposed to
advocating or counselling illegal acts. I note
that in any event these examples
would likely fall within the artistic merit, medical,
educational, scientific,
or public good defences, discussed below.
59 However, it must be observed that the provision
is broad enough to capture
written works created by the author alone, solely for
his or her own eyes. For
example, the law could arguably extend to a teenager's
favourable diary account
of a sexual encounter. The interpretations of "advocates
or counsels" and the
fact that the description must be of an unlawful act
reduce the likelihood of
this happening. Nevertheless, the possibility remains
that a teenager's private
account of a sexual encounter could be caught.
This example, like that of a
drawing made and kept exclusively by the accused, engages
the value of private
self-fulfilment and appears to pose little real risk
of harm to children,
rendering it constitutionally problematic.
63 The second meaning that can be ascribed
to "artistic merit" is "possessing
the quality of art", or "artistic character". On
this meaning, a person who
produces art of any kind is protected, however crude
or immature the result of
the effort in the eyes of the objective beholder.
This interpretation seems
more consistent with what Parliament intended.
It is hard to conceive of
Parliament wishing to make criminality depend on the
worth of the accused's art.
It would be discriminatory and irrational to permit
a good artist to escape
criminality, while criminalizing less fashionable, less
able or less
conventional artists. Such an interpretation would
run counter to the need to
give the defence a broad and generous meaning.
I conclude that "artistic merit"
should be interpreted as including any expression that
may reasonably be viewed
as art. Any objectively established artistic value,
however small, suffices to
support the defence. Simply put, artists, so long
as they are producing art,
should not fear prosecution under s. 163.1(4).
69 The defence of possession for medical,
education and scientific purposes,
like the other defences, should be interpreted liberally
in accordance with
Parliament's intent.
70 "Public good" has been interpreted as "necessary
or advantageous to
religion or morality, to the administration of justice,
the pursuit of science,
literature, or art, or other objects of general interest"....
Examples of possession
of child pornography which could serve the public good
include possession of
child pornography by people in the justice system
for purposes associated with
prosecution, by researchers studying the effects of exposure
to child
pornography, and by those in possession of works addressing
the political or
philosophical aspects of child pornography. Again,
the same procedure would
apply as for the defence of artistic merit.
75 Yet problems remain. The interpretation
of the legislation suggested above
reveals that the law may catch some material that particularly
engages the value
of self-fulfilment and poses little or no risk of harm
to children. This
material may be grouped in two classes. The
first class consists of
self-created, privately held expressive materials. Private
journals, diaries,
writings, drawings and other works of the imagination,
created by oneself
exclusively for oneself, may all trigger the s. 163.1(4)
offence. The law, in
its prohibition on the possession of such materials,
reaches into a realm of
exceedingly private expression, where s. 2(b) values
may be particularly
implicated and state intervention may be markedly more
intrusive. Further, the
risk of harm arising from the private creation and possession
of such materials,
while not eliminated altogether, is low.
76 The second class of material concerns privately
created visual recordings
of lawful sexual activity made by or depicting the person
in possession and
intended only for private use. Sexually explicit
photographs taken by a
teenager of him- or herself, and kept entirely in private,
would fall within
this class of materials. Another example would
be a teenaged couple's private
photographs of themselves engaged in lawful sexual activity.
Possession of such
materials may implicate the values of self-fulfilment
and self-actualization,
and therefore, like the material in the first category,
reside near the heart of
the s. 2(b) guarantee. And like the material in
the first category, this
material poses little risk of harm to children.
It is privately created and
intended only for personal use. It depicts only
lawful sexual activity.
Indeed, because the law reaches depictions of persons
who are or appear to be
under 18, the person or persons depicted may not even
appear to be children.
Section 1 analysis:
Is the objective pressing and substantial?
82 I earlier concluded that Parliament's objective
in passing s. 163.1(4) was
to criminalize possession of child pornography that poses
a reasoned risk of
harm to children. This objective is pressing and
substantial. Over and above
the specific objectives of the law in reducing the direct
exploitation of
children, the law in a larger attitudinal sense asserts
the value of children as
a defence against the erosion of societal attitudes toward
them. While the
government in this case did not present attitudinal harm
to society at large as
a justification for the law's intrusion on the right
of free expression, this
may be seen as a good incidental to the law's main purpose
-- the prevention of
harm to children.
2 Is There Proportionality Between the Limitation
on the Right and the
Benefits of the law?
(a)Rational Connection
84 As the first step in showing proportionality,
the Crown must demonstrate
that the law is likely to confer a benefit or is "rationally
connected" to
Parliament's goal. This means that it must show
that possession of child
pornography, as opposed to its manufacture, distribution
or use, causes harm to
children.
85 This raises a question pivotal to this
appeal: what standard of proof must
the Crown achieve in demonstrating harm -- scientific
proof based on concrete
evidence or a reasoned apprehension of harm? The
trial judge insisted on
scientific proof based on concrete evidence. With
respect, this sets the bar
too high. In Butler, supra, considering the obscenity
prohibition of the
Criminal Code, this Court rejected the need for concrete
evidence and held that
a "reasoned apprehension of harm" sufficed (at p. 504).
A similar standard must
be employed in this case.
86 The Crown argues that prohibiting possession
of child pornography is linked
to reducing the sexual abuse of children in five ways:
(1) child pornography
promotes cognitive distortions; (2) it fuels fantasies
that incite offenders;
(3) prohibiting its possession assists law enforcement
efforts to reduce the
production, distribution and use that result in direct
harm to children; (4) it
is used for grooming and seducing victims; and (5) some
child pornography is
produced using real children.
McLaughlin accepted all five arguments.
89 .... The lack of unanimity in scientific
opinion is not fatal. Complex human behaviour may
not lend itself to precise
scientific demonstration, and the courts cannot hold
Parliament to a higher
standard of proof than the subject matter admits of.
Some studies suggest that
child pornography, like other forms of pornography, will
fuel fantasies and may
incite offences in the case of certain individuals.
This reasoned apprehension
of harm demonstrates a rational connection between the
law and the reduction of
harm to children through child pornography.
94 .... Only by extending the law to private possession can these harms be squarely attacked.
(b)Minimal Impairment
95 This brings us to a critical question in
this case: does the law impair the
right of free expression only minimally? If the
law is drafted in a way that
unnecessarily catches material that has little or nothing
to do with the
prevention of harm to children, then the justification
for overriding freedom of
expression is absent.
99 The fact remains, however, that the law
may also capture the possession of
material that one would not normally think of as "child
pornography" and that
raises little or no risk of harm to children: (1) written
materials or visual
representations created and held by the accused alone,
exclusively for personal
use; and (2) visual recordings, created by or depicting
the accused, that do not
depict unlawful sexual activity and are held by the accused
exclusively for
private use.
100 Possession of material in these categories
is less closely tied to harm to
children than the vast majority of material caught by
the law. Children are not
exploited in its production. The self-created nature
of the material comprising
the first category undermines the possibility that it
could produce negative
attitudinal changes. In the second category, those
depicted may well not even
look like children. This said, some material in
these categories could
conceivably cause harm to children. Self-created
private expressive materials
could conceivably abet negative attitudinal changes in
the creator, although
since the creation came from him or her in the first
place one would not expect
the effect to be significant. A self-created private
depiction or writing in
the possession of the maker could fall into the
hands of someone who might use
it in a way that harms children. Again, a person's
video or photo of him- or
herself engaged in a lawful sexual act could present
an image that looks like a
child, which could possibly come into the hands of someone
who would use it to
harm children. So it cannot be denied that permitting
the author of such
materials to keep them in his or her custody poses some
risk. However, the risk
is small, incidental and more tenuous than that associated
with the vast
majority of material targeted by s. 163.1(4). Indeed,
the above-cited examples
lie at the edge of the problematic classes of material.
The bulk of the
material in these two problematic classes, while engaging
important values
underlying the s. 2(b) guarantee, poses no reasoned risk
of harm to children.
(c)Proportionality: the Final Balance
102 This brings us to the third and final
branch of the proportionality
inquiry: whether the benefits the law may achieve in
preventing harm to children
outweigh the detrimental effects of the law on the right
of free expression. The
final proportionality assessment takes all the elements
identified and measured
under the heads of Parliament's objective, rational connection
and minimal
impairment, and balances them to determine whether the
state has proven on a
balance of probabilities that its restriction on a fundamental
Charter right is
demonstrably justifiable in a free and democratic society.
103 In the vast majority of the law's applications,
the costs it imposes on
freedom of expression are outweighed by the risk of harm
to children. The Crown
has met the burden of demonstrating that the possession
of child pornography
poses a reasoned apprehension of harm to children and
that the goal of
preventing such harm is pressing and substantial.
103 Explicit sexual photographs of children, videotapes
of pre-pubescent children, and written works advocating
sexual offences with
children -- all these and more pose a reasoned risk of
harm to children. Thus
we may conclude that in its main impact, s. 163.1(4)
is proportionate and
constitutional.
105 However, the prohibition also captures
in its sweep materials that
arguably pose little or no risk to children, and that
deeply implicate the
freedoms guaranteed under s. 2(b). The ban, for
example, extends to a
teenager's sexually explicit recordings of him or herself
alone, or engaged in
lawful sexual activity, held solely for personal use.
It also reaches private
materials, created by an individual exclusively for him
or herself, such as
personal journals, writings, and drawings.
It is in relation to these
categories of materials that the costs of the prohibition
are most pronounced.
At the same time, it is here that the link between the
proscribed materials and
any risk of harm to children is most tenuous, for the
reasons discussed earlier:
children are not exploited or abused in their production;
they are unlikely to
induce attitudinal effects in their possessor; adolescents
recording themselves
alone or engaged in lawful sexual activity will generally
not look like
children; and the fact that this material is held privately
renders the
potential for its harmful use by others minimal. Consequently,
the law's
application to these materials, while peripheral to its
objective, poses the
most significant problems at this final stage of the
proportionality analysis.
107 I turn first to consider the law's application
to self-created works of
the imagination, written or visual, intended solely for
private use by the
creator. .... Personal
journals and writings, drawings and other forms of visual
expression may well be
of importance to self-fulfilment. Indeed, for young
people grappling with
issues of sexual identity and self-awareness, private
expression of a sexual
nature may be crucial to personal growth and sexual maturation.
The fact that
many might not favour such forms of expression does not
lessen the need to
insist on strict justification for their prohibition.
As stated in Irwin Toy,
supra, at p. 976, "the diversity in forms of individual
self-fulfilment and
human flourishing ought to be cultivated in an essentially
tolerant, indeed
welcoming, environment".
D.Remedy
111 Confronted with a law that is substantially
constitutional and
peripherally problematic, the Court may consider a number
of alternatives. One
is to strike out the entire law. ....
112 Another alternative might be to hold that
the law as it applies to the
case at bar is valid, declining to find it unconstitutional
on the basis of a
hypothetical scenario that has not yet arisen.
In the United States, courts
have frequently declined to strike out laws on the basis
of hypothetical
situations not before the court, although less so in
First Amendment (free
expression) cases.
113 Yet another alternative might be to uphold
the law on the basis that it is
constitutionally valid in the vast majority of its applications
and stipulate
that if and when unconstitutional applications arise,
the accused may seek a
constitutional exemption.
114 I find it unnecessary to canvas any of
these suggestions further because
in my view the appropriate remedy in this case is to
read into the law an
exclusion of the problematic applications of s. 163.1,
following Schachter v.
Canada, [1992] 2 S.C.R. 679. Schachter suggests
that the problem of peripheral
unconstitutional provisions or applications of a law
may be addressed by
striking down the legislation, severing of the offending
sections (with or
without a temporary suspension of invalidity), reading
down, or reading in. The
Court decides on the appropriate remedy on the basis
of "twin guiding
principles": respect for the role of Parliament,
and respect for the purposes
of the Charter (at p. 715). Applying these principles,
I conclude that in the
circumstances of the case reading in an exclusion is
the appropriate remedy.
115 To assess the appropriateness of reading
in as a remedy, we must identify
a distinct provision that can be read into the existing
legislation to preserve
its constitutional balance. In this case, s. 163.1
might be read as
incorporating an exception for the possession of:
1 Self-created expressive material: i.e.,
any written material or visual
representation created by the accused alone, and held
by the accused alone,
exclusively for his or her own personal use; and
2 Private recordings of lawful sexual activity:
i.e., any visual recording,
created by or depicting the accused, provided it does
not depict unlawful sexual
activity and is held by the accused exclusively for private
use.
117 These two exceptions would necessarily
apply as well to the offence of
"making child pornography" under s. 163.1(2) (but not
to printing, publishing or
possessing for the purpose of publishing); otherwise
an individual, although
immune from prosecution for the possession of such materials,
would remain
vulnerable to prosecution for their creation.
126 The legislative history of Bill C-128,
which introduced s. 163.1(4),
reinforces my view that reading in an exclusion of the
problematic material
would not unduly intrude on the legislative domain.
As was noted during the
Senate Committee's proceedings, there had over the years
been a great deal of
debate, both within Parliament and in the country more
generally, about the
problem of child pornography and the appropriate way
to address it (Proceedings
of the Standing Senate Committee on Legal and Constitutional
Affairs, Issue No.
50, June 21, 1993, at p. 50:41 (statement of Richard
Mosley, Chief Policy
Counsel, Criminal and Social Policy, Department of Justice)).
127 After expressing concern over the potential
for constitutional problems
arising from Bill C-128, the Honorable Gérald-A.
Beaudoin, Chairman of the
Senate Committee, concluded:
There is, obviously, also the problem the
courts will face. The Supreme
Court of Canada has to interpret the Constitution and
the Criminal Code. If the
legislation is very vague, greater power is given to
the judges. This is a
difficulty which, in cases involving obscenity and pornography,
perhaps, cannot
be avoided. In other words, to a certain extent
it has to be left to the
courts.
(Proceedings of the Standing Senate Committee
on Legal and Constitutional
Affairs, Issue No. 51, June 22, 1993, at p. 51:54.)
As Senator Beaudoin predicted, it has fallen
to the Courts to interpret s.
163.1(4) and judge its ultimate validity in accordance
with that interpretation.
The British Columbia Courts found the law
constitutionally wanting and struck
it down in its entirety. I too, find it to be constitutionally
imperfect.
However, the defects lie at the periphery of the law's
application. In my view,
the appropriate remedy is to uphold the law in its broad
application, while
holding that it must not be applied to two categories
of material, as described
above: self-created, privately held expressive materials
and private recordings
that do not depict unlawful sexual activity.
* * * * * * * * * * *
Here are some excerpts from the minority decision, which was written by Claire L'Heureux-Dubé.
L'HEUREUX-DUBÉ, GONTHIER AND BASTARACHE JJ. -
131 In this appeal, we are asked to assess
the constitutionality of s.
163.1(4) of the Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46.
The Court must determine
whether Parliament may legitimately criminalize the possession
of the material
it has defined as child pornography. Specifically,
we must decide whether s.
163.1(4) is an unjustified infringement of the right
to free expression found in
s. 2(b) of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms.
The Court is also asked
to determine whether s. 163.1(4) infringes s. 7 of the
Charter. In our view,
the s. 7 liberty interest is encompassed in the right
of free expression and
proportionality falls to be considered under s. 1.
Accordingly, no separate s.
7 analysis is required.
153 While the guidelines set out in Oakes
provide a useful analytical
framework for the practical application of s. 1, it is
important not to lose
sight of the underlying purpose of that section, namely
to balance individual
rights and our communal values. Where courts are
asked to consider whether a
violation is justified under s. 1, they must be sensitive
to the competing
rights and values that exist in our democracy.
As Dickson C.J. advised in
Oakes, supra, at p. 136:
The Court must be guided by the values and
principles essential to a free and
democratic society which I believe embody, to name but
a few, respect for the
inherent dignity of the human person, commitment to social
justice and equality,
accommodation of a wide variety of beliefs, respect for
cultural and group
identity, and faith in social and political institutions
which enhance the
participation of individuals and groups in society.
The underlying values and
principles of a free and democratic society are the genesis
of the rights and
freedoms guaranteed by the Charter and the ultimate standard
against which a
limit on a right or freedom must be shown, despite its
effect, to be reasonable
and demonstrably justified.
155 More recently, this Court has emphasized
that close attention must be paid
to the factual and social context in which an impugned
provision exists at each
stage of the s. 1 analysis. In Thomson Newspapers,
supra, Bastarache J., for
the majority of this Court, stated as follows, at para.
87:
The analysis under s. 1 of the Charter must
be undertaken with a close
attention to context. This is inevitable as the
test devised in R v. Oakes,
[1986] 1 S.C.R. 103, requires a court to establish the
objective of the impugned
provision, which can only be accomplished by canvassing
the nature of the social
problem which it addresses. Similarly, the proportionality
of the means used to
fulfil the pressing and substantial objective can only
be evaluated through a
close attention to detail and factual setting.
In essence, context is the
indispensable handmaiden to the proper characterization
of the objective of the
impugned provision, to determining whether that objective
is justified, and to
weighing whether the means used are sufficiently closely
related to the valid
objective so as to justify an infringement of a Charter
right.
158 The very existence of child pornography,
as it is defined by s. 163.1(1)
of the Criminal Code, is inherently harmful to
children and to society. This
harm exists independently of dissemination or any risk
of dissemination and
flows directly from the existence of the pornographic
representations, which on
their own violate the dignity and equality rights of
children. The harm of
child pornography is inherent because degrading, dehumanizing,
and objectifying
depictions of children, by their very existence, undermine
the Charter rights of
children and other members of society. Child pornography
eroticises the
inferior social, economic, and sexual status of children.
It preys on
preexisting inequalities.
159 The Report on Pornography by the Standing
Committee on Justice and Legal
Affairs (1978) (MacGuigan Report), spoke of the effects
of pornography as
follows (at p. 18:4):
The clear and unquestionable danger of this
type of material is that it
reinforces some unhealthy tendencies in Canadian society.
The effect of this
type of material is to reinforce male-female stereotypes
to the detriment of
both sexes. It attempts to make degradation, humiliation,
victimization, and
violence in human relationships appear normal and acceptable.
A society which
holds that egalitarianism, non-violence, consensualism,
and mutuality are basic
to any human interaction, whether sexual or other, is
clearly justified in
controlling and prohibiting any medium of depiction,
description or advocacy
which violates these principles.
160 In a similar manner, child pornography
creates a type of attitudinal harm
which is manifested in the reinforcement of deleterious
tendencies within
society. The attitudinal harm inherent in child
pornography is not empirically
measurable, nor susceptible to proof in the traditional
manner but can be
inferred from degrading or dehumanizing representations
or treatment; see
Thomson Newspapers, supra, at para. 92, and R. v. Mara,
[1997] 2 S.C.R. 630. In
the past this Court has not held Parliament to a strict
standard of proof in
showing a link between the expressive activity in question
and the harm which it
seeks to prevent, but has afforded Parliament a margin
of appreciation to pursue
legislative objectives based on less than conclusive
social science evidence;
see Irwin Toy, supra, at p. 990; Keegstra, supra, at
p. 776; Butler, supra, at
p. 504.
161 In Butler, supra, this Court recognized
that some forms of pornography
create attitudinal harm. Butler concerned an accused
who was charged with
various counts related to selling, possessing for the
purposes of distribution
and exposing obscene materials that did not involve children.
While considering
the meaning of obscenity within the context of s. 163(8)
of the Criminal Code,
Sopinka J., writing for the majority, stated, at p. 479,
that degrading and
dehumanizing material would, apparently, fail the community
standards test
not because it offends against morals but because it
is perceived by public opinion
to be harmful to society, particularly to women.
While the accuracy of this
perception is not susceptible of exact proof, there is
a substantial body of opinion
that holds that the portrayal of persons being subjected
to degrading or dehumanizing
sexual treatment results in harm, particularly to women
and therefore to society
as a whole.
167 In short, the lack of scientific precision
in the social science evidence
relating to attitudinal harm available to Parliament
is not a valid reason for
calling into question Parliament's decision to act.
It has been estimated that
over 60,000 Canadians have been depicted at a young age
in sexually explicit
material; see Badgley Report, supra, vol. 2, at p. 1198.
It goes without saying
that child pornography which sexually exploits children
in its production is
harmful. Moreover, we have seen that the harms
of child pornography extend far
beyond direct, physical exploitation. It is harmful
whether it involves real
children in its production or whether it is a product
of the imagination. In
either case, child pornography fosters and communicates
the same harmful,
dehumanizing and degrading message.
170 Canadian society has always recognized
that children are deserving of a
heightened form of protection. This protection
rests on the best interests of
the child. The vulnerability of children is a product
of the innate power
imbalance that exists between adults and children.
As a result of this
vulnerability, children are often targets of violence
and exploitation. It has
been estimated that in almost 80 percent of sex crimes
committed, the victims
are girls, boys and young men and women under the age
of 20; see N. Bala and M.
Bailey, "Canada: Recognizing the Interests of Children"
(1992-93), 31 U.
Louisville J. Fam. L. 283, at p. 292. Fully two-thirds
of sexual assault
victims in 1993 were children, and one-third of all victims
were under the age
of 10; see J.V. Roberts, "Sexual Assault in Canada:
Recent Statistical Trends"
(1996), 21 Queen's L.J. 395, at p. 420. Indeed,
it is thought that one in four
girls and one in 10 boys will be victims of sexual assault
before they reach the
age of 18; see R. Bessner, "Khan: Important Strides
Made by the Supreme Court
Respecting Children's Evidence" (1990), 79 C.R. (3d)
15, at p. 16.
181 The nature of the expressive activity
at issue is another important
contextual factor that has emerged from the Court's s.
2(b) jurisprudence. The
Court has emphasized that under s. 1, the level of protection
to which
expression is entitled will vary with the nature of the
expression. The more
distant the expression from the core values underlying
the right, the more
likely action restricting it can be justified; see Keegstra,
supra, at p. 765;
Lucas, supra, at para. 34. Defamatory libel, hate
speech and pornography are
far removed from the core values of freedom of expression
and have been
characterized as low value expression, which merits an
attenuated level of
constitutional protection; see Lucas, supra, at para.
93; Butler, supra, at p.
500; Keegstra, supra, at p. 765.
183 It is clear that the possession of child
pornography contributes nothing
to the search for truth. The impugned provision
prohibits the possession of
material which visually depicts children engaged in sexual
activity or which has
as its dominant characteristic the depiction, for a sexual
purpose, of the
sexual organ or the anal region of a child. The
written material prohibited is
that which advocates or counsels the commission of sexual
offences against
children. The message conveyed by child pornography
perpetuates lies about
children's humanity. It promotes the false view
that children are appropriate
sexual partners and that they are sexual objects to be
used for the sexual
gratification of adults. It encourages and condones
their sexual abuse. These
messages contribute nothing to the search for truth and
are in fact detrimental
to that search.
185 The expression at issue in this case is
linked to the value of
self-fulfilment, but only in a limited sense since s.
163.1(4) of the Criminal
Code in no way impedes positive self-fulfilment.
In Butler, supra, the Attorney
General for Ontario argued that the only value underlying
pornography as a form
of expression was self-fulfilment in its most base aspect,
that of pure physical
arousal (at pp. 499-500). We find this argument
particularly apposite in
relation to child pornography. Child pornography
is used to fuel the fantasies
of paedophiles and is also used to facilitate their exploitation
of children.
It hinders children's own self-fulfilment and autonomous
development by
eroticising their inferior social, economic and sexual
status. It reinforces
the message that their victimization is acceptable.
In our view, that message
denies children their autonomy and dignity. In
relation to adult pornography,
Sopinka J. found in Butler that such expression does
not stand on an equal
footing with other kinds of expression which directly
engage the "core" of the
freedom of expression values (at p. 500). We agree
with this statement and find
it equally applicable in the context of child pornography.
186 The possession of child pornography has
no social value; it has only a
tenuous connection to the value of self-fulfilment underlying
the right to free
expression. As such, it warrants only attenuated
protection. Hence, increased
deference should be accorded to Parliament's decision
to prohibit it.
189 Child pornography also undermines children's
right to life, liberty and
security of the person as guaranteed by s. 7. Their
psychological and physical
security is placed at risk by their use in pornographic
representations. Those
children who are used in the production of child pornography
are physically
abused in its production. Moreover, child pornography
threatens the physical
and psychological security of all children, since it
can be encountered by any
child. Regardless of its authorship, be it of the
child or others, it plays on
children's weaknesses and may lead to attitudinal harm;
....
We recognize that privacy is an important value
underlying the right to be free from unreasonable search
and seizure and the
right to liberty. However, the privacy of those
who possess child pornography
is not the only interest at stake in this appeal.
The privacy interests of
those children who pose for child pornography are engaged
by the fact that a
permanent record of their sexual exploitation is produced.
This privacy
interest is also triggered when material which is created
by teenagers in a
"consensual environment" is disseminated.
B. Application of the Oakes Test
1. Is the Objective Pressing and Substantial?
yes
2. Proportionality
(a) Rational Connection
yes
(b) Minimal Impairment
211 In conducting an analysis of whether s.
163.1(4), in combination with the
definition of "child pornography" set out in s. 163.1(1),
minimally impairs the
right to free expression, the Court must be particularly
sensitive to the
contextual factors which we have previously discussed.
212 As Cory J. recognized in Lucas, supra,
at para. 57, the negligible value
of the expression restricted is an important factor in
the minimal impairment
analysis, ....
215 In concluding that the objective outweighs
the harm done to the right
protected by s. 2(b), I have considered that s. 172 reaches
inside the home.
That reach is a significant aggravating feature when
considering the harm done
by the section to the right of freedom of expression.
That same feature,
however, is essential if the section is to serve its
purpose. Unfortunately, it
is in the home where children are most susceptible to
the kinds of conduct at
which s. 172 is aimed.
225 We turn now to the second ground upon
which Rowles J.A. found that s.
163.1(4) did not minimally impair the s. 2(b) guarantee,
namely that the
provision applies to teenagers between the ages of 14
and 17 who keep videotapes
or pictures of themselves engaged in explicit sexual
activity or who keep
pictures of themselves, the dominant purpose of which
is the depiction of their
sexual organs or anal regions for a sexual purpose.
In our view, when viewed in
its context, this effect of the provision is a reasonable
limit on teenagers'
freedom of expression.
227 In R. v. Geisel, Man. Prov. Ct., February
2, 2000, the accused was found
in possession of 22 photographs of teenaged girls in
various states of undress.
In some of the photographs one of the teenaged girls
was engaged in sexual
activity with a teenaged boy. The accused had befriended
the girls and had
allowed one of them to stay at his house when she ran
away from home. The girls
would visit the accused and he would take photographs.
Before taking the
photographs the accused would provide the girls with
alcohol which he described
to them as "liquid cocaine" because it was so strong.
In Jewell, supra, the
accused Gramlick produced his own pornographic videotapes
involving 12 children
whose ages ranged from 11 to 17. Five of the boys
were under the age of 14 and
were filmed engaging in sexual acts with each other and
with adult men,
including a prostitute. The boys used in the pornography
"were generally
described as being from impoverished and broken homes"
(p. 274). They were
enticed into performing by rewards of money, cigarettes
and gifts. The other
accused, Jewell, videotaped his sexual activities with
12 boys, the youngest of
whom was 10 years old. Some of them had no knowledge
that they were being
filmed. Again, money, cigarettes and alcohol were
used as bribes. "In some
instances, [Jewell] posed as a friendly father figure,
who disguised his house
as a place of refuge when the young boys left their homes.
He took some of the
boys on trips unavailable to them in their own homes,
to places like Disneyworld
in Florida and Canada's Wonderland. There was evidence
that he shared these
boys with Gramlick and other associates" (p. 276).
228 A recent case before this Court further
reveals the exploitation that can
occur once pornographic representations of adolescents
exist. In R. v. Davis,
[1999] 3 S.C.R. 759, the accused was charged with sexually
assaulting several
complainants. One of the complainants was 15-16
years old at the time. The
accused had posed as a photographer who could launch
the complainant's modelling
career. He took nude photographs of the complainant
and afterwards refused to
show them to her. Eventually she asked for the
negatives of the pictures. The
accused told her that if she wanted the negatives she
would have to perform
sexual acts with him, and that if she refused, he would
send the photographs to
her mother.
229 These cases illustrate the very real harm
which can be visited upon
adolescents between the ages of 14 and 17. In each
one, however, the
exploitation involved in the production of the pornographic
videotapes and
pictures would not be evident from viewing them.
It is impossible, from looking
at a picture, to determine that the adolescent depicted
therein has not been
exploited. Hence, Parliament had a strong basis
for concluding that the age
limit in the definition of child pornography should be
set at 18 in order to
protect all children from the harm of being used in the
production of child
pornography. The provision recognizes, as do ss.
153 and 212(4) of the Criminal
Code, that while adolescents may be capable of consenting
to sexual activity,
their consent is vitiated in circumstances where there
is a possibility that
they may be exploited.
231 Thus, we cannot agree with the approach
to this issue taken by McLachlin
C.J. The inclusion of teenage pornography in s.
163.1(4) is consistent with the
legislative purpose of providing for the effective protection
of children by
reducing the potential for harm caused by pornographic
material. McLachlin C.J.
is not persuaded that auto-depictions of teenage sexual
activity are harmful.
With respect, Parliament was justified in restricting
teenagers from creating a
permanent record of their sexual activity. While
adolescents between the ages
of 14 and 17 may legally engage in sexual activity, the
creation of a permanent
record of such activity has consequences which children
of that age may not have
sufficient maturity to understand, as illustrated in
Davis, supra. Furthermore,
the Fraser Committee recognized that children, because
of their vulnerability,
are not always accorded the same autonomy as adults.
It states (vol. 2, at p.
561):
232 In considering whether s. 163.1(4), in
conjunction with the definition of
child pornography, minimally impairs the guarantee of
freedom of expression, it
is important to bear in mind that the provision does
not amount to a total ban
on the possession of child pornography. The provision
reflects an attempt by
Parliament to weigh the competing rights and values at
stake and achieve a
proper balance. First, the definitional limits
act as safeguards to ensure that
only material that is antithetical to Parliament's objectives
in proscribing
child pornography will be targeted. Second, the
legislation incorporates
defences of artistic merit, educational, scientific or
medical purpose, and a
defence of the public good. With regard to the
defence of artistic merit,
McLachlin C.J. writes that "[a]ny objectively established
artistic value,
however small" (para. 63), provides a complete defence.
In our view, the
boundaries of the artistic merit defence do not need
to be decided in this
appeal, especially since the defence also applies to
the prohibition against the
publication, distribution and sale of child pornography
that are also found in
s. 163.1. However, we would consider anomalous
interpreting artistic merit to
provide a complete defence in a case in which the same
material would fail the
artistic merit test under the obscenity provisions of
the Criminal Code. We
must give effect to Parliament's deliberate decision
to avoid the term artistic
"purpose", which it adopted for the educational, scientific
and medical
defences. Artistic merit must be determined with
regard to composition and
emphasis according to the criteria described in para.
64 of McLachlin C.J.'s
reasons and through careful attention to artistic conventions,
expert opinions
and modes of production, display and distribution.
Simply calling oneself an
artist is not an absolute shield to conviction.
233 In light of the analysis above, we conclude
that Parliament has enacted a
law which is appropriately tailored to the harm it seeks
to prevent. Therefore,
we conclude that the impugned provision minimally impairs
the rights guaranteed
by s. 2(b).
(c) Proportionality of Effects
The benefits of the prohibition of the possession
of child
pornography far outweigh any deleterious effect on the
right to free expression.