Classics in the History of Psychology
An internet resource developed by
Christopher D. Green
ISSN 1492-3713
(Return to index)
By E. B. TITCHENER (1895)
First published in Mind, 4, 506-514.
Posted
December 2001
In a recent
number of the Psychological Review[1] Professor Baldwin has proposed a
"type-theory" of the simple reaction,
which he opposes to the theory of "a certain mental Anlage or aptitude" as held by
"Wundt, Külpe and others." I
wish to examine this type-theory partly on its own merits, and partly in the
light of the· conclusion of my previous article on "Simple Reactions[2]."
A few preliminary
remarks seem necessary to the full understanding of the issue. (1) The "theory" of the simple
reaction, in the sense in which the word is used by the Leipsic investigators
(Wundt, Lange, Martius, Hiilpe,
etc.), consists in the analysis of' the whole process into its constituent
part-processes, physiological, psychophysical and psychological, and in the
reference of the two latter kinds
of part-process to their conditions, physiological or psychological. The theory has undergone very considerable
modification between 1887 and 1895: so that the Leipsic names cannot be simply
bracketed together, as they are by Professor Baldwin. A "disposition" or "aptitude" theory does
not exist. (2) What the term
"disposition" in this connection really means can best be shown by quotations[3]. Lange writes: "Our experience shows that
there are certain persons who are incapable...... of reacting consistently in
the sensorial or muscular way
throughout an experimental series, however good their intention and however
complete their practice. They are too
nervous, too distraught; and they fail into such a state of general mental
excitement that they ordinarily do not even possess sufficient presence of mind
to disclaim the reactions which they know to have been wrongly executed. It would, of course, be useless for the
normal psychologist to make experiments upon subjects in so obviously
pathological a condition. [p. 507] -- It is to be noted that individuals who
are usually sure of their reactions may lapse into this condition for a day at
a time[4].*" Wundt says:
"You will find during the course of practice that there are individuals who
are entirely incapable of any steady concentration of the attention, and who
will therefore never make trustworthy subjects.
That should not be surprising. It
is not everyone who has the capacity for astronomical or physical observation;
and it is not to be expected either that everyone is endowed with the gifts
requisite for psychological experimentation.*"
The type-theory sets
out from the proposition that "the current distinction between sensory and
motor reactions does not hold in the sense that the motor reaction is always
shorter than the sensory."
"Individual differences are clearly established." Then,
reaching his conclusion by way of the pathology of the speech function
(aphasia), Professor Baldwin argues that "a man is an 'auditive,' or a
'visual' or a 'motor' in his voluntary movements generally....... If this be true, it is evident that a man's
reaction time will show the influence of his memory-type. The motor reaction we should expect to be
most abbreviated in the man of the motor type; and less abbreviated, or not so
at all, in the 'visual' or 'auditory' man." "In simple hand movements [as in speech] people must show
the sensory and motor types" For the man of the motor type, "the
thought of movement is the most facile beginning of the movement, just because
it is really the movement, and nothing else, that he thinks of."
"The man who gives relatively shorter sensory reactions is a 'sensory' in his type: with him the
attempt to think of the movement as a movement interferes with the
prompt and exact execution of it, just because he is not accustomed to execute
his movements in that way."
It is clear that
these sentences constitute the outline of a theory in the strict sense; i.e.,
that " type" cannot be paralleled with
"disposition." It is also clear
that the theory is an, attempt at the specific formulation of the conditions of
those divergences to which Külpe refers only in general terms, and that the
formulation has ii good measure of aprioristic probability. Külpe, however, believes in the normality of
the sensorial-muscular difference: Professor Baldwin does not[5].
Some of Professor Baldwin's evidence, it is true, was inaccessible to
Külpe. We must ask whether the testimony
of the new experiments is sufficient to turn the scale.
Evidence for the
type-theory.-- The evidence in
favour of any scientific theory is ordinarily of two kinds, constructive and
circumstantial.[p. 509] The constructive
evidence furnishes a direct experimental verification of the hypothesis; the circumstantial
evidence consists in the demonstration of the ability of the hypothesis to
account for facts left unexplained by previous hypotheses. Professor Baldwin
draws upon both categories of proof. But it is a grave defect in his
constructive argument that not one of the subjects to whose reaction times he
appeals is recorded to have been specially tested for type-memory, The obvious plan would surely be to make
certain of the type first, and then obtain reactions. There are many methods of testing type, apart
from the reaction method.
Four persons reacted to sound. Two of them, B. and S., carried out the
investigation of which the present Study is a report: presumably, therefore,
they had the type-theory in mind throughout. Whether the other two reacted with
or without knowledge we are not told. The reactions were of the following
kinds: sensory (sensorial), kinaesthetic motor (attention "given to the
movement by thought of the hand, the eyes being blindfolded"), visual
motor (attention "fixed upon the hand, which is seen"), light sensory
(sensorial as before), dark
sensory (sensorial in dark room), light motor (kinæsthetic motor, as before),
and dark motor (kinæsthetic motor in dark room). Although nos. 1 and 4 and nos.
2 and 6 are identical, the times are given in different tables, and not
compared. Tabulating, we have, in values of s:
The greatest reliance is placed upon the
times of B. and S. But, in the first place, the fourth line of the tables shows
that neither of these subjects reacts constantly. In one 1000 experiments, B. gives 149s and S.
184; in another 1000, B. gives 164, and S. 158. If this variation is not due to
imperfect practice, it calls for special explanation. Secondly: Professor Baldwin tells ns that he
used to react in the sensorial-muscular way*.
The differences between his sensory and motor reactions amount here only
to 29, 7, 12, and 46s, in the different cases.
How has this change come about? Thirdly:
Professor Baldwin, in drawing conclusions from the two Tables, argues from
time-differences (22, 18, 21s) which fall within the
limits of the mean variation of the total times (10 to 20s; no specific figures given). Nevertheless, it
must be admitted that the Tables show some striking results, and that the
construction of types from them is very ingenious.
Much emphasis
is laid by Professor Baldwin upon a case reported [p. 510] by Professor Flournoy[6], in which the difference
between the time of reaction with sensorial attention and that with motor attention
was not a positive 100s, but on the average a
negative 110s. The reagent was incapable of the true "muscular reaction," i.e., of
reaction "with special preparation of the muscles" M. Flournoy writes
of him as follows. "There is no
sign of the preparatory [muscular] tension which is one of the characters of
the true muscular reaction. And this is not due to any
misunderstanding, but to a physical impossibility
....... Whenever he has attempted at my request to give his muscles a certain
degree of preliminary tension, he has fallen into the other extreme, and
produced a permanent contraction of the whole arm." This contracture
appears to the reagent to be a "fatiguing and unnatural operation, which
does not assist the reaction in any way."
"When the attention is motor," in the manner normal to him,
"it is the perception or visual image of his right arm which fills his
thoughts." For him "motor
attention is always attention
to the visual form of the movement."
"He is distracted by the visual image." M. Flournoy characterises him as a visuel géometrique, as distinguished from a visuel pittoresque. "He has no
coloured hearing, but possesses schemata, perfectly definite and
localised, for the series of numbers, the week, the year, etc."
It is unnecessary to
go into further detail either as regards the mentality of the reagent, or M.
Flournoy's analysis of his time results.
The facts present no difficulty to the Leipsic theorists,-- who can
accept them, just as they accept the facts of differences [p. 511] of
memory-type, and can also accept the explanation offered of them. All that they
would say is that the "physical impossibility" to react muscularly is
not, in laboratory experience, a feature of the normal or average mental constitution,
any more than number-forms are.
Consequently, the mind so constituted cannot be drawn upon to furnish
norms of reaction : however interesting its workings may be in other
connections.
Circumstantial evidence is found by Professor Baldwin in certain results
published by Cattell, and (doubtfully) in times obtained from Donders. With regard to the former Professor Cattell
writes to me as follows:--
"I have always found it difficult to define my own 'memory-type' by
introspection. I presume that I am what would be called 'verbal motor.'
The length of my reaction-time does not seem to be affected by the direction of attention. The observer J. also gave the same reaction-time, whether attention were directed to the stimulus or the movement. · I am
not able to define the 'memory-type' of this observer: but it is not strongly visual. The third observer, D., is a professor of biology and is by nature and training visual; his reaction-time was much lengthened when he attended to the movement, he having normally always attended to the sensation. I presume that his case would support the theory of Flournoy and Baldwin. My own idea is that An unusual direction of the attention lengthens the reaction-time, but that when the reaction has been much practised it becomes reflex. In my own case it requires practically no attention of any sort.
I can, however, give you an instance (unpublished) that supports your point of view. An observer reacted much more slowly for sound than for light. When I enquired into the matter I found that it was because his attention was disturbed (i.e. was sensory) by not knowing where the sound was. When I shewed him the place and nature of the sound, his reaction became much quicker and more regular."
Honours are divided. But it is plain
enough that we cannot infer type from reaction, whatever may be the effect of type upon reaction, given equality of all other conditions.
The Donders times are 180s for sound, and 188 a for light. Wundt explains the first as sensorial and the second as muscular, 'referring the difference to practice[7]. Donders had reacted to light far more frequently then to sound. Of course, he may have been a 'visual' as Professor Baldwin guesses. But I have so far been unable to find any indication of the fact in the literature: and Wundt's hypothesis is well borne out by the last case cited in Professor Cattell's letter.
Professor Baldwin does not claim support for his theory from the other times which do not show the sensorial-muscular difference, quoted in my previous paper.
Evidence against the type-theory.-- "There are as many kinds of memory," writes Volkmann[8] "as there are kinds of ideas." True, it is probable that inequality of memories in the same [p. 512] individual is the rule,
not the exception[9]." But there seems to be no good ground for the
assumption that this inequality is, on the average, so great as to pass over
into a virtually exclusive preponderance of one particular memory. Most people, I imagine, would judge by
Jacob's voice and by the hands of Esau, though they might incline, by
nature or education, to prefer either one of the two criteria. In other words, a "mixed"
memory-type must be recognised.
The elucidation of a
memory-type is by no means an easy matter.
No memory-image is
qualitatively constant, even if it persist in
its original type. Very frequently it
does not: many would-be visual
memories are in reality verbal (auditory) memories, --we remember that we "saw" things of which we have
merely heard our elders speak;
or we say that we remember "seeing" when all that we really remember
is the form of words in which we are accustomed to narrate the experience. Type
may shift in other ways: it is possible to break oneself of the habit of piano playing
by finger-memory, and to learn to "read," i.e. to very from the
motor type to the sensory. In my own experience, memory-type differs
considerably, and not always quite accountably, as between special
recollections and actions[10].
I have tested and
observed the processes of memory in myself since 1890. By nature, my visual memory is the strongest;
the motor is available, but a good deal weaker; the auditory lags
still farther behind the motor than the motor does behind the visual. Having
satisfied myself of these relations, I attempted, in 1891 and 1892, to have
special practice to the motor and auditory types; and succeeded in largely
increasing their effectiveness. Since
1892 I have been engaged in experiments which have demanded an exclusively visual memorising: and the results
show that the effort to rule out conflicting processes has been
successful. Yet my visual and auditory
reactions, sensorial and muscular,
have varied only by a few s
during the five years. Moreover, the time-difference showed itself
from the moment that I had learned the two possibilities of direction of attention,
slid before I· knew anything of what 'ought' to happen upon Lange's theory.
Professor Baldwin
thinks that distinctions will manifest themselves, within the sensory type, in
the times of reaction to stimuli from various sense-departments. A 'visual,' e.g., will react
more quickly to light than to sound.
Indeed, this belief is essential to the type-theory of reactions. As I
have said above, the theory is [p. 513] a "generalisation" from the facts of aphasia. "Voluntary movements generally"
will be performed as the speech-movements are performed: the "cue"
for reaction will be the "cue" normal to speech, in the given
case. M. Binet, who appears to have
arrived independently of Professor Baldwin at a similar conclusion, regards the
results of his test of M. Inaudi as invalidating the hypothesis[11]. M. Inaudi is a professional
"calculator," of the pure auditory type. The auditory 'cue,' i.e.,
is very strongly predominant in his calculations. There is also a motor 'cue,' but "the
movement of articulation only intervenes to reinforce the auditory image."
Visual ideation is exceedingly
elementary. The reaction-times were: sound, 86s;
sight, 89s; touch, 88s. M.
Binet writes:
"The
average time of reaction remains almost exactly the same, 0.08 sec., whatever
the nature of the stimulus. One would
have supposed that M. Inaudi, whose type is for all
practical purposes exclusively auditory would react
most quickly to auditory stimuli. We
even imagined at the time that the reaction method could be employed for the determination
of the memory-type of different persons.
The hypothesis, perhaps, is still not wholly untenable: it may be that
experiments upon hysterical subjects would furnish interesting results. But at any rate, it has broken down
completely in the case of M. Inaudi."
Professor Baldwin may fairly object that the test is not unexceptionable,
as no comparison was instituted
between the sensorial and muscular directions of attention. In any event,
however, the results appear to tell heavily against the type-theory. If the times are "sensory" they
should have shown difference. From the
Leipsic standpoint they would be judged to be muscular: (1) because M. Inaudi was new to the reaction experiment, and so would be
apt to concentrate his attention upon the hand movement; (2) because of their
shortness; (3) because of their small mean variation (10s);and (4) because of
their uniformity in the different sense-departments. If we grant that they are muscular, we
have a man, endowed with an extraordinarily developed sense memory, preferring
muscular times, and giving no sign of any inclination to change to the opposite
form,-- as the theory requires; while the muscular
times are so short that it would be impossible for the sensorial to be shorter,--
as the theory again requires.
M. Binet bows to the facts.
"It must not be supposed that M. Inaudi
is an auditive outside of his professional exercises in calculation. He is an auditive for calculation, i.e. for
one partial, special, sharply defined memory: there is nothing to show that he is guided by audition in the
use of his other faculties." One
cannot argue, with Professor Baldwin, from the "cues, checks,
controls," involved in speech to those "affixed to hand actions." A man may speak from predominantly sensory
'cues,' and yet execute a true muscular reaction from a motor: indeed, he may
prefer to take the motor cue for reaction, when he is left free to choose between
that and the sensory. [p. 514]
To these two
negative instances must be added the weight of all the evidence for the
generality of the sensorial-muscular difference.
As the argument has been somewhat overweighted
with details, it may not be amiss to append a brief summary:
(1) Only a certain proportion of
those who offer themselves for test in the psychophysical laboratory prove to
be capable of constant and regular reaction.
Hence I have spoken of a "disposition" for these psychological
experiments.
(2) The great majority of those who react with
constancy show the sensorial-muscular difference. Hence I have taken this difference as averagely indicative of the
psychological "disposition."
(3) Those who react regularly,
but not in the sensorial-muscular way, require special attention at the hands
of the experimenter. Their times may be
explained by degree of practice (so Wundt
of Donders), by automatism[12] from continued practice
(Wundt of Cattell, Cattell of himself), by abnormality (uncommon feature) of
mental constitution (Flournoy's case), by the character of their reaction
education (Dessoir's cases), by novelty of stimulus (Martius) by insufficient education (van Biervliet's
cases), etc.
(4) Upon the basis of the foregoing propositions
a theory of the simple reaction has been built up. Its stages have been briefly sketched in
previous papers in Mind. It is
connected with the names of Wundt, L. Lange, Martius,
Münsterberg, Külpe, etc.
(5) Professor Baldwin offers as a substitute for
this theory a theory couched in terms of memory-type. Reaction time is an index of the type of
'cue' used by the subject in speaking.
The sensorial-muscular difference is not a fact from which inferences can
be drawn for theory. There is no reason
why the sensorial time should be averagely longer than the
muscular. Sensory speakers react more
quickly sensorially than muscularly, and vice versa.
(6) The new theory certainly possesses something
of the "naturalness and probability" which is claimed for it by its
author. But the evidence for it at present is so slight that it is hardly more
than a; conjecture. It seems fair to say
that no unequivocal testimony has been adduced, while the counter-evidence is
very strong.
If the a priori probability
be still emphasised, the objection must be urged that the theory, in its
present form, is much too simple. The
memory mechanism is more
complex than Professor Baldwin recognises.
E. B. TITCHENER.
Footnotes
[1] Vol. II. no. 3, May, 1895.
[2] Mind, Jan. 1895, pp. 74 ff.
[3]
This particular word has, I believe, been used by myself only. Cf. l.c.
p. 78: "The distinction drawn by L. Lange [between sensorial and
muscular simple reactions] is a
valid one, but not obtainable from every observer. Rather is there required for
the work a special kind of disposition or Anlage."
[4]
All passages marked with an asterisk in this Discussion are exactly cited in my previous paper.
[5] It is hardly necessary to remind the reader
that the Leipsic "sensorial-muscular difference and Professor Baldwin's
"sensory and motor types" are quite different things.
[6] Professor Baldwin writes (p. 265):
"Titchener, in his summing up, does not cite the cases of Flournoy nor the
earlier report of one of my present cases (F.) in the [N.Y.] Medical Record, April
15, 1893, although they tell directly against his own views....... [He] is…
wrong in citing me as favouring the position [of Lange and Wundt]."
I have quoted a remark from Professor Baldwin's report on p. 79. I did
not mention it on p. 77 because the reading of it gave me no idea that the
author had turned his back upon the sensorial-muscular difference, as a
fundamental fact. In the light of later statements (that in the Psych. Rev., and that in Mental Development, I.
p. 465) it is easy to see that
I mistook his meaning,-- for which I am
very sorry. The report itself is a preliminary note, without figures.
On p. 79 I have
also mentioned M. Flournoy. When I wrote, I had not succeeded in obtaining his
articles: I knew them only from Ebbinghaus' summary
in the Zeitschr. f.·Psych.
(V. pp. 406, 407) and from Philippe's abstract in the Rev. phil. (XXXV. p. 444).
They were not cited on p. 77 for the reason that they seemed to me to be
irrelevant to the issue. The mechanism
of the visual reagent's mind appeared to be as exceptional as that of Stricker's, e.g. Hence I regarded the case as one to
be treated apart from the question of the normal or average variations of
reaction-time.
The quotations in
the text are from M. Flournoy's second paper (Arch. Des sci. phys, et nat., XXVIII
pp. 319 ff.). I think that they justify
my original opinion. Of the former
article (XXVII. p. 575) the author writes to me: "It was only a
preliminary note, very brief, and not giving any figures."
[7] Physiol. Psych.; 4th ed. II. pp. 322, 313.
[8] Lehrbuch
d. Psych., 3rd ed. I. p.
476.
[9] Ribot: Les maladies de la mémoire,
7th ed, pp. 110, 111.
[10]
Cf. Baldwin, Mental Development, pp. 435,461, note. Ch. XIV. XV. of this
work call attention to certain of the facts noticed above; but their generalisations
appear to be one-sided. Such, at least,
is the indication of the details of evidence which I have been able to collect.-- The only explicit recognition of a "mixed" type
by Professor Baldwin that I can find occurs in the Phil. Rev., II. p. 396:-- (article on " Internal Speech and Song)." Elsewhere, type is treated as if necessarily
simple.
[11] Psychol.
des grands calculateurs, etc. 1894, pp. 106
ff. 69, 72.
[12] It is to be noted that automatism can only arise where a considerable
amount of practice has preceded the attempt to get the sensorial-muscular
difference. I have never known the difference, once obtained, to decrease. It
rather tends to increase as the sensorial time is constant, but there is great
difficulty in the retention of the muscular form intact. Hence I must differ
entirely from professor Baldwin, Psych. Rev., II. p. 270.