Shyam Ranganathan
Home About Me Research Publications Books Contact

I am a translation theorist and translator. These two aspects of my work grew organically. While I wrote a dissertation on translation, I decided to translate a philosophical text from Sanskrit because I could not stand the translations on the market. Getting involved with the scholarly challenge of translation had a marked influence on my philosophical views and translation theory. It further undermined, for me, a common view in the literature that the object of translation is the linguistic meaning of what is said and that the content of thought is this meaning.  This is the assumed view of philosophers in the Western tradition in both the Analytic and Continental traditions, from what I could tell: it underwrote the kinds of skeptical arguments about translation we find in philosophy (from philosophers as dissimilar as Quine and Derrida) , but also the optimistic views about translation we find entertained (as seen in the moral semantics literature).  My research and practice of translation also directed me to the conclusion that a common and influential view in the Translation Studies literature (championed by the likes of Eugene Nida) is mistaken too. According to this account, accurate or good translation reproduces the pragmatic effects of the original texts, but in the target audience. (It’s a modern version of a theory that was long ago entertained and rejected by Russell and Wittgenstein: a functional theory of meaning.) So if a text made people laugh in the original, then a good translation has to do the same according to this account. While this might seem appropriate in the case of fiction or drama, it’s unreasonable to expect that this has any bearing on philosophy, science, law, mathematics–disciplines where truth matters. For the pragmatics of  statements is a largely subjective and inter-subjective matter, and the topic of philosophy, law, science or mathematics is not subjective or inter-subjective.


One commonality in the literature, I observed, whether inside or outside of philosophy, was a tendency to describe translation as a one-size fits all exercise, but one that had primarily to do with linguistics.  


My response was to observe hat there is no such thing as translation as such: one always translates works of a specific kind. This is why translators must specialize in specific disciplines. This is because:

This approach corresponds to our best translation practices employed in the support of research in the academy and in matters such as law.  It also entails the following:

This implies that there are many processes of semiotic conversion aimed at user friendliness  that are not translation, but localization.  It also entails other interesting findings for the philosophy of thought:

The only reason for denying these last observation is what seems like a stubborn commitment to the idea that the meaning of what we say in our language is propositional content. The problem with this position is that it entails something funny:

The real problem though for the linguistic approach to thought is that it has to settle on an account of meaning that is bound to linguistic contexts–-specific languages. But the principle means of distinguishing between the pragmatic and the semantic is that the semantic transcends contexts, while the pragmatic does not.  So linguistic accounts of thought end up settling with a pragmatic account of meaning, which is ironic. The way we avoid this irony is by identifying semantic content and propositional content as what transcends languages in translation, but this is only possible if we allow that accuracy in translation is judged along disciplinary lines for this disciplinarity allows us to identify the meaning of a text as something that transcends the contingencies of the culture that defines and gives rise to resources that compose it in the first place.  

We can and do identify the meaning of utterances in languages, and we can and do identify the literal meaning of such utterances in terms of their systematic or basic role in a language. This is something important for disciplines such as lexicography and linguistics, but not for others.


One of the most important outcomes of this approach to thought, meaning and translation is that:





Philosophy of Translation